Artistic creation depends on a tension between
two opposing forces, which Nietzsche terms the “Apollonian” and the
“Dionysian.” Apollo is the Greek god of light and reason, and Nietzsche
identifies the Apollonian as a life- and form-giving force, characterized by
measured restraint and detachment, which reinforces a strong sense of self.
Dionysus is the Greek god of wine and music, and Nietzsche identifies the
Dionysian as a frenzy of self-forgetting in which the self gives way to a
primal unity where individuals are at one with others and with nature. Both the
Apollonian and the Dionysian are necessary in the creation of art. Without the
Apollonian, the Dionysian lacks the form and structure to make a coherent piece
of art, and without the Dionysian, the Apollonian lacks the necessary vitality
and passion. Although they are diametrically opposed, they are also intimately
intertwined.
Nietzsche suggests that the people of ancient
Greece were unusually sensitive and susceptible to suffering and that they
refined the Apollonian aspect of their nature to ward off suffering. The primal
unity of the Dionysian brings us into direct apprehension of the suffering that
lies at the heart of all life. By contrast, the Apollonian is associated with
images and dreams, and hence with appearances. Greek art is so beautiful
precisely because the Greeks relied on the appearances generated by images and
dreams to shield themselves from the reality of suffering. The early, Doric
period of Greek art is dull and prim because the Apollonian influence too
heavily outweighs the Dionysian.
The Greek tragedies of Aeschylus and Sophocles,
which Nietzsche considers to be among humankind’s greatest accomplishments,
achieve their sublime effects by taming Dionysian passions by means of the
Apollonian. Greek tragedy evolved out of religious rituals featuring a chorus
of singers and dancers, and it achieved its distinctive shape when two or more
actors stood apart from the chorus as tragic actors. The chorus of a Greek
tragedy is not the “ideal spectator,” as some scholars believe, but rather the
representation of the primal unity achieved through the Dionysian. By
witnessing the fall of a tragic hero, we witness the death of the individual,
who is absorbed back into the Dionysian primal unity. Because the Apollonian
impulses of the Greek tragedians give form to the Dionysian rituals of music
and dance, the death of the hero is not a negative, destructive act but rather
a positive, creative affirmation of life through art.
Unfortunately, the golden age of Greek tragedy
lasted less than a century and was brought to an end by the combined influence
of Euripides and Socrates. Euripides shuns both the primal unity induced by the
Dionysian and the dreamlike state induced by the Apollonian, and instead he
turns the Greek stage into a platform for morality and rationality. Rather than
present tragic heroes, Euripides gives his characters all the foibles of
ordinary human beings. In all these respects, Nietzsche sees Socrates’
influence on Euripides. Socrates effectively invented Western rationality,
insisting that there must be reasons to justify everything. He interpreted
instinct as a lack of insight and wrongdoing as a lack of knowledge. By making
the world seem knowable and all truths justifiable, Socrates gave birth to the
scientific worldview. Under Socrates’ influence, Greek tragedy was converted
into rational conversation, which finds its fullest expression in Plato’s
dialogues.
The modern world has inherited Socrates’
rationalistic stance at the expense of losing the artistic impulses related to
the Apollonian and the Dionysian. We now see knowledge as worth pursuing for
its own sake and believe that all truths can be discovered and explained with
enough insight. In essence, the modern, Socratic, rational, scientific
worldview treats the world as something under the command of reason rather than
something greater than what our rational powers can comprehend. We inhabit a
world dominated by words and logic, which can only see the surfaces of things,
while shunning the tragic world of music and drama, which cuts to the heart of
things. Nietzsche distinguishes three kinds of culture: the Alexandrian, or
Socratic; the Hellenic, or artistic; and the Buddhist, or tragic. We belong to
an Alexandrian culture that’s bound for self-destruction.
The only way to rescue modern culture from
self-destruction is to resuscitate the spirit of tragedy. Nietzsche sees hope
in the figure of Richard Wagner, who is the first modern composer to create
music that expresses the deepest urges of the human will, unlike most
contemporary opera, which reflects the smallness of the modern mind. Wagner’s
music was anticipated by Arthur Schopenhauer, who saw music as a universal
language that makes sense of experience at a more primary level than concepts,
and Immanuel Kant, whose philosophy exposes the limitations of Socratic
reasoning. Not coincidentally, Wagner, Schopenhauer, and Kant are all German,
and Nietzsche looks to German culture to create a new golden age.
We have no direct understanding of myth anymore,
but we always mediate the power of myth through various rationalistic concepts,
such as morality, justice, and history. So far, the tremendous influence of
Greek culture has done very little to shift our own culture’s opposition to art
because we tend to interpret the Greeks according to our own standards and read
tragedies as expressions of moral, rational forces rather than expressions of
the mythic forces of the Apollonian and the Dionysian. Myth gives us a sense of
wonder and a fullness of life that our present culture lacks. Nietzsche urges a
return to our deeper selves, which are entwined in myth, music, and tragedy.
Analysis
Nietzsche’s concept of the Dionysian, which he
refines and alters over the course of his career, stands as a pointed
counterbalance to the thoroughgoing rationality that is so prominent in most
philosophy. In most scholarly investigations, the importance of truth and
knowledge are taken as givens, and thinkers trouble themselves only over
questions of how best to achieve truth and knowledge. By contrast, Nietzsche
questions where this drive for truth and knowledge come from and answers that
they are products of a particular, Socratic view of the world. Deeper than this
impulse for truth is the Dionysian impulse to give free rein to the passions
and to lose oneself in ecstatic frenzy. We cannot properly appreciate or
criticize the Dionysian from within a tradition of rationality because the Dionysian
stands outside rationality. As much as the civilized world may wish to deny it,
the Dionysian is the source of our myths, our passions, and our instincts, none
of which are bounded by reason. While the civilizing force of the Apollonian is
an essential counterbalance—contrary to some stereotypes of Nietzsche, he is
firmly against the complete abandonment of reason and civilization—Nietzsche
warns that we lose the deepest and richest aspects of our nature if we reject
the Dionysian forces within us.
For Nietzsche, art is not just a form of human activity but is
rather the highest expression of the human spirit. The thrust of the book is
well expressed in what is perhaps its most famous line, near the end of section
5: “it is only as an aesthetic phenomenon that
existence and the world are eternally justified.” One of
Nietzsche’s concerns in The Birth of Tragedy is
to address the question of the best stance to take toward existence and the
world. He criticizes his own age (though his words apply equally to the present
day) for being overly rationalistic, for assuming that it is best to treat
existence and the world primarily as objects of knowledge. For Nietzsche, this
stance makes life meaningless because knowledge and rationality in themselves
do nothing to justify existence and the world. Life finds meaning, according to
Nietzsche, only through art. Art, music, and tragedy in particular bring us to
a deeper level of experience than philosophy and rationality. Existence and the
world become meaningful not as objects of knowledge but as artistic
experiences. According to Nietzsche, art does not find a role in the larger
context of life, but rather life takes on meaning and significance only as it
is expressed in art.
By attacking Socrates, Nietzsche effectively
attacks the entire tradition of Western philosophy. While a significant group
of Greek philosophers predate Socrates, philosophy generally identifies its
start as a distinctive discipline in Socrates’ method of doubt, dialogue, and
rational inquiry. While Nietzsche acknowledges that Socrates gave birth to a
new and distinctive tradition, he is more interested in the tradition that
Socrates managed to replace. Greek tragedy as Nietzsche understands it cannot
coexist in a world of Socratic rationality. Tragedy gains its strength from
exposing the depths that lie beneath our rational surface, whereas Socrates
insists that we become fully human only by becoming fully rational. From
Socrates onward, philosophy has been the pursuit of wisdom by rational methods.
In suggesting that rational methods cannot reach to the depths of human
experience, Nietzsche suggests that philosophy is a shallow pursuit. True
wisdom is not the kind that can be processed by the thinking mind, according to
Nietzsche. We find true wisdom in the Dionysian dissolution of the self that we
find in tragedy, myth, and music.
Nietzsche wrote The Birth of Tragedy at
a time when he was most heavily under Wagner’s influence. Nietzsche had met
Wagner as a young man and was deeply honored when Wagner chose to befriend him.
Wagner impressed his own views on life and art on Nietzsche, and The Birth of Tragedy is, in many ways, a
philosophical justification for the work Wagner was carrying out in his operas.
Over the course of the 1870s, however, Nietzsche became increasingly
disillusioned with Wagner, and his mature works, starting with Human, All-Too-Human, show Nietzsche finding his own
distinctive voice, free from Wagner’s influence. In particular, Nietzsche
became disgusted with Wagner’s shallow pro-German nationalism and his
anti-Semitism. In contrast to Nietzsche’s later biting attacks on nationalism,The Birth of Tragedy bears Wagner’s influence in
its pride in German culture and its hope that a purified German culture can
rescue European civilization from the deadening influence of Socratic
rationalism.
Apollo was the Greek
god of truth, light, and order; Dionysus, the god of fertility, passion,
spontaneity, and rebellion. Apollo and Dionysus represent polarities of the
human personality: the logical, orderly side, and the intuitive, spontaneous
side. The German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche originally made the
distinction between these two gods and their characteristics. Inside each of
us, he said, Apollo and Dionysus wage a war for dominance, with the two sides
vying with one another for dominance in various aspects of our personal lives,
including activities as simple as walking.The obvious solution is to strive for
a balance between these two mighty forces, a struggle made more difficult by
the fact that these opposing elements also manifest themselves in institutions
such as religion and education. The study of the humanities can help balance
these oppositions because even if the content of much art is full of Dionysian
emotion, its form is Apollonian.
Main article: The Birth of Tragedy
Nietzsche's aesthetic usage of the concepts, which was later developed
philosophically, was first developed in his book The Birth of Tragedy, which was published in 1872. His major premise here was that the
fusion of Dionysian and Apollonian "Kunsttrieben"
("artistic impulses") forms dramatic arts, or tragedies. He goes on
to argue that this fusion has not been achieved since the ancient Greek
tragedians. Nietzsche is adamant that the works of Aeschylus and Sophocles represent the apex of artistic creation,
the true realization of tragedy; it is with Euripides, he states, that tragedy begins its "Untergang"
(literally "going under", meaning decline, deterioration, downfall,
death, etc.). Nietzsche objects to Euripides' use of Socratic rationalism in his
tragedies, claiming that the infusion of ethicsand reason robs tragedy of its foundation, namely the
fragile balance of the Dionysian and Apollonian.
The relationship between the Apollonian and Dionysian
juxtapositions is apparent, Nietzsche claimed in The Birth of Tragedy,
in the interplay of Greek Tragedy: the tragic hero of the drama, the main
protagonist, struggles to make order (in the Apollonian sense) of his unjust
and chaotic (Dionysian) Fate, though he dies unfulfilled in the end. For the
audience of such a drama, Nietzsche claimed, this tragedy allows us to sense
an underlying essence, what he called the "Primordial Unity", which
revives our Dionysian nature - which is almost indescribably pleasurable.
Though he later dropped this concept saying it was “...burdened with all the
errors of youth” (Attempt at Self Criticism, §2), the overarching theme was a
sort of metaphysical solace or connection with the heart of creation.
Different from Kant's idea of the sublime, the Dionysian is
all-inclusive rather than alienating to the viewer as a sublimating experience.
The sublime needs critical distance, while the Dionysian demands a closeness of
experience. According to Nietzsche, the critical distance, which separates man
from his closest emotions, originates in Apollonian ideals, which in turn
separate him from his essential connection with self. The Dionysian embraces
the chaotic nature of such experience as all-important; not just on its own,
but as it is intimately connected with the Apollonian. The Dionysian magnifies
man, but only so far as he realizes that he is one and the same with all
ordered human experience. The godlike unity of the Dionysian experience is of
utmost importance in viewing the Dionysian as it is related to the Apollonian
because it emphasizes the harmony that can be found within one’s chaotic
experience.
Apollo
(Apollonian or Apollinian): the dream state or the wish to create order,
principium individuationis (principle of individuation), plastic (visual) arts,
beauty, clarity, stint to formed boundaries, individuality, celebration of
appearance/illusion, human beings as artists (or media of art's manifestation),
self-control, perfection, exhaustion of possibilities, creation, the
rational/logical and reasonable.
Dionysus
(Dionysian): chaos, intoxication, celebration of nature, instinctual,
intuitive, pertaining to the sensation of pleasure or pain, individuality
dissolved and hence destroyed, wholeness of existence, orgiastic passion,
dissolution of all boundaries, excess, human being(s) as the work and
glorification of art, destruction, the irrational and non-logical.
No comments:
Post a Comment